Skip to document
This is a Premium Document. Some documents on Studocu are Premium. Upgrade to Premium to unlock it.

The basis of legal sovereignty

law
Module

Contract Law (LAWS10021)

173 Documents
Students shared 173 documents in this course
Academic year: 2023/2024
Uploaded by:
Anonymous Student
This document has been uploaded by a student, just like you, who decided to remain anonymous.
University of Manchester

Comments

Please sign in or register to post comments.

Preview text

THE BASIS OF LEGAL SOVEREIGNTY

H. W. R. WADE

THE great South African case of Harris v. Minister of the Interior 1

will have turned the thoughts of many lawyers to the subject

of legal sovereignty. Under English law the principle of the

sovereignty of Parliament, " the dominant characteristic of our

political institutions," 2 is supposed to be something very simple

and clear—and so indeed it appears in its classic exposition in

the pages of Dicey. But the classic exposition is now widely

controverted; an example may be taken from the recent remark

of the Lord President of the Court of Session 3 :

" As is well known, the conflict between academic logic and

political reality has been emphasised by the recent South

African decision as to the effect of the Statute of Westminster

—Harris v. Minister of the Interior."

What is more, on the rare occasions when courts in England or

the Commonwealth find themselves concerned with the validity

of Acts of Parliament, further conflicts are revealed in the comments

of text-writers who discuss these cases. There seems to be a

widening rift between the orthodox propositions which the courts

lay down and the speculative deductions of critics who delve

deeper beneath the surface towards the bedrock of constitutional

theory. Inferences which to many people would seem to be

1 1952 (2) S. 428; [1952] 1 T.L. 1245; Keir and Lawson Cases in Con-

stitutional Law (4th ed.) 506. For comment on the case see 68 L.Q.

285; 65 Harv.L. 1361; 30 Can.B. 692, 734; 31 Can.B. 52. After

losing this case the South African Government attempted to achieve its ends

by establishing special courts for such questions, since the legislature has

power to establish courts of law without recourse to the " entrenched " proce-

dure; but the Act constituting Parliament itself into such a court was held

illegal: Minister of the Interior v. Harris and Others, 1952 (4) S. 769.

The government has now procured legislation for increasing the number of

appellate judges and the number of Senators: Appeal Court Quorum Act,

1955; Senate Act, 1955.

A most valuable commentary on the principal case will be found in

Professor D. V. Cowen's two articles on " Legislature and Judiciary " in

15 M.L. 282 and 16 M.L. 273, to which as will be seen the present

article is much indebted. Its object is not to survey further the voluminous

literature on sovereignty, but to attempt .to bring to a head the current

controversies on the subject. In a sense, therefore, it starts at the point

where Professor Cowen leaves off, for after his excellent account of the

background and the arguments of both sides he concludes that the fundamentals

of the subject are " fluid, elusive and obscure."

2 Dicey, Law of the Constitution (9th edition by Professor E. C. S. Wade), 39.

3 MacCormick v. Lord Advocate, 1953 S. 396 at p. 412.

172

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 173

merely corollaries of propositions laid down by the courts can be

shown to conflict with the beliefs of such authorities as Dicey,

Anson, Sir Ivor Jennings, Sir David Keir, Professor Lawson and

Professor Friedmann. Nor are they all of the same mind among

themselves. The more deeply the subject is explored, the more

one is inclined to suspect that the bedrock will turn out to be

quicksand.

All writers on sovereignty are bound to deal in improbable

examples. One has to ask what would happen if Parliament tried

to abdicate, or to alienate its powers, or to impose restrictions

on future legislation after the manner of the South African

entrenched clauses. In England these may seem academic

questions; but the improbable case will often throw light on the

actual. For example, all the argument in Harris v. Minister of

the Interior proceeded on the assumption that the central question

—whether the " entrenched " clauses of the South African con-

stitution were still entrenched since the Statute of Westminster—

was; a strictly legal one, to which there was a right or a wrong

answer, according to the existing law. But, if one first considers

the abstract question of the alienability of sovereign power, one

may reach the conclusion that the issue before the South African

courts was fundamentally different from any other ordinary legal

issue, and that the courts were really called upon for a political

or legislative decision, having no " law " to guide them, but having

to create new law in a situation which should strictly be called

revolutionary. The theoretical analysis, if it is accepted, then

makes it easier to understand the reasoning followed by the Appel-

late Division in deciding the case.

Another case which is bound to be in the forefront of the

discussion is Att.-Gen. for New South Wales v. Trethowan,* the

well-known decision of the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council.

Although that case was, on a narrow view, no more than a

decision on a particular provision of the Colonial Laws Validity

Act, 1865, its highly interesting set of facts has been made the

basis of some remarkable predictions about the power of the

Parliament of the United Kingdom. After nearly twenty-five years

it is still a source of thought-provoking comments, which doubtless

has not yet run dry. This is all the more remarkable since the

case in no way raised any question of the validity of acts of a

sovereign legislature, but was rather concerned with subordinate,

or delegated, legislative power. This paradoxical situation is

typical of the subject, for the English courts have hardly ever

* [1932] A. 526.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 175

a referendum; and that, as one must also postulate if the example

is to hold good for a sovereign legislature, any repealing Act not

so approved should be void and of no effect. Next suppose that

Parliament, wishing to retrace its steps, passes a repealing Act

by its ordinary procedure, with no referendum, and the royal

assent is duly given. Is the repeal effective? The orthodox answer

is in the affirmative, and at least three well-known judicial decisions

can be cited: Vauxhall Estates, Ltd. v. Liverpool Corporation 6 ;

Ellen Street Estates, Ltd. v. Minister of Health 7 ; and British

Coal Corporation v. The King.* The first two cases turned on

the provision of the Acquisition of Land (Assessment of Compen-

sation) Act, 1919, that the provisions of any Act authorising

acquisition of land, if inconsistent with the Act of 1919, " shall

cease to have or shall not have effect." Provisions which were

in certain respects inconsistent were made by the Housing Act,

1925, and it was argued that the words of the Act of 1919 made

it proof against the implied repeal which would otherwise have

occurred. This argument was rejected by the judges, and, in the

second case, by the Court of Appeal. In the Vauxhall Estates case

Avory J. said 9 :

" It must be admitted that such a suggestion as that is

inconsistent with the principle of the constitution of this

country. Speaking for myself, I should certainly hold, until

the contrary were decided, that no Act of Parliament can

effectively provide that no future Act shall interfere with its

provisions."

And in the Ellen Street Estates case Maugham L. said 10 :

" The legislature cannot, according to our constitution, bind

itself as to the form of subsequent legislation, and it is impos-

sible for Parliament to enact that in a subsequent statute

dealing with the same subject-matter there can be no implied

repeal. If in a subsequent Act Parliament chooses to make

it plain that the earlier statute is being to some extent repealed,

effect must be given to that intention just because it is the

will of the legislature."

It is important to note that Maugham L.'s statement is parti-

cularly concerned with the impossibility of requiring any particular

form for subsequent legislation, for thus his remarks extend equally

well to our imaginary example of an Act purporting to make itself

6 [1932] 1 K. 733.
7 [1934] 1 K. 590.
8 [1935] A. 500.
9 At p. 743.
10 At p. 597

176 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

unrepeatable except after a referendum. Since Parliament's power

to repeal is unqualified, it is no more possible to prescribe effectively

that a repealing Act shall be in some particular form or be enacted

by some special procedure than that there shall be no repeal at

all, or no repeal within a certain period of time. But, since

questions of " manner and form" (a phrase drawn from the

Colonial Laws Validity Act, 1865 lx) figure so prominently in this

subject, it is worth while emphasising that the question of form

was squarely before the court in the Vauxhall Estates and Ellen

Street Estates cases. This was because counsel conceded that the

Act of 1919 would have to yield to an express repeal, but

contended that its language protected it from implied repeal where

some later Act merely contained some inconsistent provision. In

other words, he contended that in 1919, by enacting that incon-

sistent provisions " shall not have effect," Parliament had altered

the rule of law which says that where two Acts of Parliament

conflict, the later repeals the earlier by implication. Since he

conceded that an express repeal would have been effective, he

was arguing in effect that the Act of 1925 was defective in form

for the purpose of repealing the Act of 1919, for want of some

formula expressly effecting the repeal. In rejecting this argument

the courts were for the same reason holding that it was just as

impossible for an Act to be made proof against implied repeal

as against express repeal. Even if this was the intention of the

Act of 1919 (which as a matter of construction was at least doubt-

ful), the will of an earlier Parliament must give way to the will

of a later Parliament. Here, therefore, were two decisions where it

was held that the law-making process was not at the mercy of

Parliament for the time being, but was guarded by the courts

in order that future Parliaments might be unfettered. That the

courts should have the function of guarding 1 this doctrine against

the provisions of an Act of Parliament is not really surprising,

since it is only an application of the principle that Parliament

cannot bind its successors. Nevertheless the conclusion that there

exists a rule of law which Parliament is incompetent to alter

challenges further analysis.

The third case, British Coal Corporation v. The King, is

familiar to all students for the memorable remark of Lord Sankey

L. (delivering the judgment of the Judicial Committee of the

Privy Council) about the possibility of repeal of the Statute of

Westminster, by which legislative independence was given to the

Dominions 12 :

11 s. 5.
12 At p. 520.

178 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

immediately afterwards to abolish the legislature without its

consent and to continue legislating by his personal decree.

" But if the prince has not supreme power, but the rule

is that the courts accept as law that which is made in the

proper legal form, the result is different. For when the prince

enacts that henceforth no rule shall be law unless it is enacted

by him with the consent of the legislature, the law has been

altered, and the courts will not admit as law any rule which

is not made in that form. Consequently a rule subsequently

made by the prince alone abolishing the legislature is not

law, for the legislature has not consented to it, and the rule

has not been enacted according to the manner and form required

by the law for the time being.

" The difference is this. In the one case there is sove-

reignty. In the other, the courts have no concern with

sovereignty, but only with the established law. ' Legal

sovereignty ' is merely a name indicating that the legislature

has for the time being power to make laws of any kind in the

manner required by the law. That is, a rule expressed to

be made by the King, ' with the advice and consent of the

Lords spiritual and temporal, and Commons in this present

Parliament assembled, and by the authority of the same,'

will be recognised by the courts, including a rule which alters

this law itself. If this is so, the ' legal sovereign ' may impose

legal limitations upon itself, because its power to change the

law includes the power to change the law affecting itself.

" This may be illustrated by a recent decision of the

Judicial Committee of the Privy Council."

Trethowan's case is then given, apparently intended as an

example of a " legal sovereign " able to impose legal limitations

on itself. The main theme is then taken up again " :

" The law is that Parliament may make any law in the manner

and form provided by the law. That manner and form is

provided, at present, either by the common law or by the

Parliament Act of 1911. But Parliament may, if it pleases,

provide another manner and form. Suppose, for instance,

that the present Parliament enacted that the House of Lords

should not be abolished except after a majority of electors

had expressly agreed to it, and that no Act repealing that

Act should be passed except after a similar referendum. There

is no law to appeal to except that Act. The Act provides

a new manner and form which must be followed unless it

17 At p. 144.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 179

can be said that at the time of its passing that Act was void

or of no effect."

Applying these alternatives to the Statute of Westminster,

section 4, the author states 18 :

" It is not possible to rebut this argument (sc. that

Parliament can lay down a binding manner and form for

future legislation) except by saying that this provision (sc.

s. 4) is void. The power of Parliament given by law, it must

be said, is not a power to pass any legislation whatever,

but a power to pass any legislation which does not limit its

own authority. Since this is a matter of common law, this

must be proved by decisions of the courts. No such proof

can be offered (though for that matter no such proof can be

offered that the other is the correct interpretation)."

Apart, therefore, from arguments founded on what Parliament

has actually done, such as the amendment of the sacrosanct terms

of the Union with Scotland Act, 1706 19 —and Jennings allows

that these, so far as they go, support Dicey 20 —we are told that

the legal position is completely obscure.

Professor Friedmann has gone further, and has stated quite

positively that the United Kingdom Parliament can bind its

successors. Discussing Trethowan's case, he writes 21 :

" Because the Colonial Laws Validity Act laid it down that

non-sovereign Parliaments, such as the New South Wales

Legislature, could make laws respecting their constitutional

powers and procedure only ' in such manner and form as may

from time to time be required by any Act of Parliament... ,'

this question has become mixed up with the distinction between

' sovereign ' and ' non-sovereign ' legislatures, which is irrele-

vant to this problem. In fact, this provision of the Colonial

Laws Validity Act only formulates a position which exists

just the same for ' sovereign legislatures ' operating under

flexible constitutions, that is, with a machinery of constitu-

tional change by simple statute. The recent shortening of

the veto power of the House of Lords from two years to one

year has brought this out... any change in the legislative

process itself must be effected in the manner and form of

the existing provisions. That a Parliament cannot fetter its

1 8 At pp. 145-6.
19 See Dicey, Law of the Constitution, 9 t h ed., 65-6, and J e n n i n g s , The Law
20 and the Constitution, 3rd ed., pp. 146-7.
B u t now see MacCormick v. Lord Advocate, note 29 below.
2' I n a n article in 24 Australian L. J. 103 (1950), at p. 104.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 181

of Parliament." Then, after a quotation from Trethowan's case, 24

they say 25 :

"... a Parliament having the same composition as the

Parliament which passed the Act requiring a referendum, and

using the same procedure, could repeal that Act. But this

only means that a skilful draftsman would protect-—or, to use

the term common in South Africa, entrench—the Act by pro-

viding that no Bill purporting to repeal it should have effect

unless approved by referendum."

This appears to mean that under English law—for it is clear

from the context that the United Kingdom Parliament is under

discussion—it is only a matter of choosing the right words for

Parliament to be able to enact entrenched clauses which will be

unrepealable except in accordance with those clauses. And, once

again, it appears to be assumed that Trethowan's case is an example

which would hold equally good in the United Kingdom. Thus

what is said to be a special subject of doubt, limited to the question

of Parliament's composition, turns out to be wide enough to include

the usual examples of " manner and form."

The exception could therefore swallow up the rule, and how

it can be reconciled with the English cases is not explained.

Would it really be possible, by the use of what is said to be a

" simple device," for the United Kingdom Parliament to make

an Act virtually unrepealable by requiring any repealing Act to

be approved by, say, ninety per cent, of the electors in a

referendum? 26 Yet hard on the heels of a conclusive quotation

from the Ellen Street Estates case follows this statement that

to entrench Acts of the United Kingdom Parliament is only a

matter of drafting.

These passages show how little confidence the leading authorities

have in the classical theory of sovereignty which Dicey propounded.

2 1 T h e quotation is the well-known passage from the j u d g m e n t of Dixon J.
(as he then was) in the H i g h Court of Australia, 44 C. L. R. at p. 426,
in which h e discussed the possible outcome of a case of the same type in
E n g l a n d. H e suggested t h a t if an Act was passed without a referendum
to repeal an Act which purported to be repealable only after a referendum,
" the courts might be called upon to consider whether the supreme legislative
power in respect of the m a t t e r had in truth been exercised in the m a n n e r
required for its authentic expression and by the elements in which it h a d
come to r e s i d e. " And he added t h a t " the answer to this question, w h e t h e r
evident or obscure, would be deduced from the principle of p a r l i a m e n t a r y
supremacy over the l a w. "
T h i s is a carefully guarded s t a t e m e n t. If, as Keir a n d L a w s o n a p p e a r
to infer, it h i n t s at the conclusion t h a t the courts would hold t h a t sovereign
power had " come to reside " in some body different from P a r l i a m e n t as
at present constituted, t h a t assumes a revolution in t h e legal system, as is
explained below.
2 5 4th ed., 7.
26 Cf. Professor F r i e d m a n n ' s r e m a r k s in 24 Australian L. J. at p. 105.

182 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

Most of the writers who have been quoted appear to realise that

somewhere in the background is a rule of English law that

Parliament cannot bind its successors. But as soon as an

example is provided, as by Trethowan's case, they hasten to abandon

this rule and suggest arguments for its opposite. These arguments

must be tested in two ways: first, are they supported by judicial

authority; secondly, can they lay claim to superior logic?

As to authority, the one and only case on which these revolu-

tionary theories have been founded is Trethowan's. That case

may be disposed of in a moment for anyone who believes in

the distinction made by Dicey—and made also, it may be added,

by the judges who decided the case—between sovereign and

subordinate legislatures. The legislature of New South Wales was

subject to the Colonial Laws Validity Act, 1865—an Act of the

sovereign Parliament at Westminster—which provided in section 5

that legislation contrary to Imperial statute was void and that

constitutional amendments must be made " in such manner and

form as may from time to time be required by any Act of

Parliament, letters patent, order in council, or colonial law for

the time being in force in the said colony." The Bill which, without

a referendum, was designed to repeal the earlier Act which declared

that it should not be repealable except after a referendum, was

undoubtedly not framed in accordance with the law " for the

time being in force." It was therefore unlawful, like any other

act of delegated power which exceeds its appointed limits. Thus

the United Kingdom Parliament, by prescribing the conditions for

the validity of legislation of the Parliament of New South Wales,

could enable it to do the one thing which the superior legislature

was incompetent to do, i., to bind its successors. There is no

paradox here. The sovereign Parliament's inability to bind its

successors arises from exactly the same cause—continuing legal

omnipotence—as the subordinate legislature's subordination. The

point was very well put by Dixon J. (as he then was) 27 :

" The difficulty of the supreme legislature lessening its own

powers does not arise from the flexibility of the constitution.

On the contrary, it may be said that it is precisely the point

at which the flexibility of the British constitution ceases to

be absolute. Because it rests upon the supremacy over the

law, some changes which detract from that supremacy cannot

be made by law effectively. The necessary limitations upon

the flexibility of the constitution of New South Wales result

from a consideration of exactly an opposite character."

" In Trethowan'x case, 44 C.L. at p. 427. See also at p. 426 for the contrast
between sovereign and subordinate legislatures.

184 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

of the type here in controversy is or is not conform to the pro-

visions of a Treaty, least of all when that Treaty is one under

which both Scotland and England ceased to be independent states

and merged their identity in an incorporating union." 32 Since

he also mentions the possibility that "nowadays there may be

room for the invocation of an ' advisory opinion' from the

International Court of Justice," 33 it seems that the Lord President's

" fundamental law " is something quite different from the ordinary

" law " which municipal courts enforce. He appears, indeed, to

safeguard himself very carefully against any suggestion that the

courts would hold Parliament unable to repeal the Union Act,

and to concern himself rather with the political propriety of

doing so.

The theory that Parliament can, under English law, lay fetters

on future Parliaments is thus, as Jennings admits, unsupported

by authority. Jennings however says that the orthodox view—

Dicey's view—also requires legal proof, and that apart from the

dictum in British Coal Corporation v. The King,3i " no such proof

can be offered." 35 But if the Ellen Street Estates case 36 is not

such proof, what is? The Court of Appeal there held, as a

necessary part of their decision, that " the legislature cannot,

according to our constitution, bind itself as to the form of sub-

sequent legislation." What more could be asked? It is not

every day that the validity of Acts of Parliament is challenged

in English courts, and one can hardly expect a long line of decisions.

A long line of professional opinions is however easily produced.

Bacon, 37 Coke 38 and Blackstone 39 are all in agreement, and every

English judge who has touched on the point has supported the

fundamental doctrine which they laid down. Why has it become

the fashion, merely because of Trethowan's case, to present this

simple English theory of Parliamentary sovereignty as if it were

full of darkness and doubt, or only some kind of bee in Dicey's

bonnet?

The explanation is probably to be found in the alluring argument

so skilfully set out by Jennings. If he appears to underrate the

3 3 " 1953 R. at p. 413.
Ibid.

####### ••>* 3 N o t e 12, a b o v e.

3 6-> The Law and the Constitution, 3rd ed., p. 146.
3 7 Notes 7 and 10, above.
See the passages quoted by Dicey, p. 64 note 2, and by Professor Cowen
in 16 M. L. E. at p. 291 from Bacon's Works, 1859 eel., Vol. V I , 159-
and Vol. V I I , 370. As to the following passage about Parliament's alleged
ability to extinguish or transfer its power, see note 69 below.
as 3 9 4 Inst. 42.
Comm. i, 9 0 : " A c t s of Parliament derogatory from the power of subsequent
parliaments bind n o t. " The phrase derives from Coke, 4 Inst. 42.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 185

legal authority against his view, no one can deny the attractions

of his own reasoning. The essence of his point is that legal

sovereignty is a doctrine of law, and that since Parliament can

change the law in any way it likes it can alter the law about

itself, and the operation of its Acts, just as well as the law about

anything else. The law is, he suggests, that a rule expressed

to be made by Crown, Lords and Commons will be recognised

by the courts, including a rule which alters this law itself. Parlia-

ment has often legislated about itself, and it is tempting to treat

the Parliament Acts, 1911 and 1949 (as Jennings, like Keir and

Lawson, does treat them) as Acts which alter the law as to

the manner and form of the exercise of the sovereign legal power.

Jennings indeed dislikes the term " sovereign," 40 in its legal sense,

for this very reason, since he inclines to the view that Parliament's

legal power rests on a legal rule, established in the courts, that

" the courts accept as law that which is made in the proper legal

form." Possibly that theory is made more plausible by the fact

that the same rule is found in the Colonial Laws Validity Act. But

that, in view of the entirely different nature of delegated power,

can be no more than an analogy. However, if the law is that

the courts recognise whatever is enacted in " the proper legal

form," then it seems to follow that an Act passed contrary to

the requirements of some previous Act (for example, without a

referendum) would not be passed " in the proper legal form "

and so would not be a valid Act of Parliament. Therefore

Parliament can bind its successors as to manner and form, and

the " sovereignty " of future Parliaments is qualified and precarious.

It can at least be conceded that this would be a perfectly

possible state of affairs. There is no absurdity in supposing that

the Imperial Parliament could be subject to the same restrictions

as the Parliament of New South Wales, i., that the common

law and the Colonial Laws Validity Act are similar in effect.

That the supposition is contrary to all available English authority

may for the moment be forgotten while its purely logical impli-

cations are explored. But, if it is to stand against the weight

both of judicial decisions and of centuries of general agreement,

something more is needed than an absence of absurdity. A rival

theory must at least be logically stronger than the conventional

theory if it is to be worth discussing. From the pride of place

which Jennings gives to his own theory it is clear that he favours

*° The Law and the Constitution, 3rd ed., 138-40. Jennings truly says that
legal sovereignty is a lawyer's concept expressing the relations between
Parliament and the courts. But his statement that it is "not sovereignty
at all," because it is not the same as political sovereignty, is hard to follow.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 187

But to deny that Parliament can alter this particular rule of law

is not so daring as it may seem at first sight; for the sacrosanctity

of the rule is an inexorable corollary of Parliament's continuing

sovereignty. If the one proposition is asserted, the other must be

conceded. Nevertheless some further justification is called for,

since there must be something peculiar about a rule of common

law which can stand against a statute.

The peculiarity lies in this, that the rule enjoining judicial

obedience to statutes is one of the fundamental rules upon which

the legal system depends. * That there are such rules, and that

they are in a very special class, is explained with great clarity

by Salmond":

" All rules of law have historical sources. As a matter of

fact and history they have their origin somewhere, though

we may not know what it is. But not all of them have legal

sources. Were this so, it would be necessary for the law

to proceed ad infinitum. in tracing the descent of its principles.

It is requisite that the law should postulate one or more

first causes, whose operation is ultimate and whose authority

is underived.... The rule that a man may not ride a bicycle

on the footpath may have its source in the by-laws of a

municipal council; the rule that these by-laws have the force

of law has its source in an Act of Parliament. But whence

comes the rule that Acts of Parliament have the force of law?

This is legally ultimate; its source is historical only, not legal.

... It is the law because it is the law, and for no other

reason that it is possible for the law itself to take notice of.

No statute can confer this "power upon Parliament, for this

would be to assume and act on the very power that is to be

conferred." 44

Once this truth is grasped, the dilemma is solved. For if

no statute can establish the rule that the courts obey Acts of

Parliament, similarly no statute can alter or abolish that rule.

The rule is above and beyond the reach of statute, as Salmond

so well explains, because it is itself the source of the authority

tit statute. 45 This puts it into a class by itself among rules of

4 3 Jurisprudence, 10th ed. (by Dr. Glanvilla Williams), 155. Professor Cowen
in 15 M.Li. 294 mentions this passage in connection with the present
status in South Africa of the South Africa Act, 1909, but not in connection
with the wider questions raised in his second article in 16 M.L. 273. For
the similarity between Salmond's " ultimate legal principle " and Kelsen's
Grundnorm, see J. W. Jones, Historical Introduction to the Theory of Laic,
4 4 22G.
4 5 Italics supplied.
The same point is made by Professor E. C. S. Wade, following Mr. E. T. E.
L a t h a m , in the 9th ed. of Dicey, p. xxxviii: " Where the purported sovereign

188 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

common law, and the apparent paradox that it is unalterable

by Parliament turns out to be a truism. The rule of judicial

obedience is in one sense a rule of common law, but in another

sense—which applies to no other rule of common law—it is the

ultimate political fact upon which the whole system of legislation

hangs. Legislation owes its authority to the rule: the rule does

not owe its authority to legislation. To say that Parliament can

change the rule, merely because it can change any other rule,

is to put the cart before the horse.

For the relationship between the courts of law and Parliament

is first and foremost a political reality. Historical illustrations of

this are plentiful. When Charles I was executed in 1649 the courts

continued to enforce the Acts of the Long Parliament, the Rump,

Barebones' Parliament, and the other Commonwealth legislatures.

For a revolution took place, and the courts (without any authority

from the previous sovereign legislature) spontaneously transferred

their allegiance from the King in Parliament to the kingless

Parliaments. In other words, the courts altered their definition

of " an Act of Parliament" and recognised that the seat of

sovereignty had shifted. This was a political fact from which

legal consequences flowed. But in 1660 there was a counter-

revolution : Charles II was restored, and it was suddenly discovered

that all Acts passed by the Commonwealth Parliaments were void

for want of the royal assent. The courts, again without any prior

authority, shifted their allegiance back to the King in Parliament,

and all the Commonwealth legislation was expunged from the

statute book. 46 The " glorious revolution " of 1688 was, in its

legal aspect if in no other, much like the revolution of 1649,

for the courts, recognising political realities but without any legal

justification, transferred their obedience from James II to William

and Mary. Had the Jacobite rebellions of 1715 and 1745 succeeded,

the courts might once again have held all intervening legislation—

including the Bill of Rights and Act of Settlement—void for lack

of the assent of the proper monarch. 47 The fact that William and

is anyone but a single actual person, rules are required to ascertain the
will of the sovereign. They must be observed as a condition of the validity
of legislation. The rules are therefore logically superior to the sovereign."
^s Maitland, Constitutional History, 282. In Heath v. Pryn (1670) 1 Vent. 14
counsel had the hardihood to challenge an Act of the Restoration Parliament:
" The plaintiff's counsel would have denied the Act of 12 Car. to be an
Act of Parliament because they were not summoned by the King's writ;
but the judges would not admit it to be questioned, and said, that all
the judges resolved, that the Act being made by King, Lords and Commons
they ought not now to pry into any defects of the circumstance of calling
47 them together.. ."
Maitland, Constitutional History, 284-5.

190 The Cambridge Law Journal [1955]

of law that the distinction is fundamental. For in the one case,

that of the sovereign legislature, there is an ultimate fact which

the legislature is itself powerless to change by legislation; while

in the other, that of the non-sovereign legislature, the authority

of its Acts can at any time be modified by the superior legislature.

That is why, as a matter of law, the United Kingdom Parliament

can empower the Parliament of New South Wales to do the one

thing which it is itself powerless to do, to wit, bind its successors.

Trethowan's case is a perfect illustration.

If this is correct, Dicey, and the many others who have held

similar views, are on firmer ground than their critics—not only

because they have the support of such judicial authority as can

be collected, but also because there happens to be a rational

foundation for what English lawyers have commonly believed.

All arguments seem to combine in support of the view that the

United Kingdom Parliament is, in the eyes of the English courts,

a continuously sovereign legislature, which cannot bind its suc-

cessors as to "manner and form" or anything else; and that

if a " skilful draftsman" attempted to entrench an Act of the

United Kingdom Parliament by forbidding repeal except after a

referendum, that Act like any other could be repealed by an

ordinary Act of Crown, Lords and Commons without a referendum.

To suggest the contrary is to assume a revolution, in which the

courts must be taken to have abandoned their loyalty to the legis-

lature as now constituted; but, since this is something which no

legislation can bring about, it is a purely political forecast.

Of course, revolutions can and do occur. Nor need we go

back to the seventeenth century for examples, for something of

the kind is undoubtedly in progress within the British Common-

wealth. South Africa provides the clearest example. The one

point which was agreed on all hands in Harris v. Minister of the

Interior was that the Parliament of the Union of South Africa

was a sovereign legislature. Thirty years ago it was undoubtedly

a subordinate legislature, for it was subject to the Colonial Laws

Validity Act just like the Legislature of New South Wales. 51 During

these years the seat of sovereign legal power has therefore shifted

from Westminster to Pretoria. How has this come about? One

naturally answers that it is the result of the Statute of Westminster,

1931, and of South Africa's own Status of the Union Act, 1934,

which in section 2 declared:

this problem," i., to the discussion of Trethowan's case. He is therefore
compelled to differ from the conclusions so convincingly stated by Dison J.:
see p. 182, above.
" R. v. Ndobe, 1930 A. 484, at 492-3.

C.L. The Basis of Legal Sovereignty 191

" The Parliament of the Union shall be the sovereign legis-

lative power in and over the Union, and notwithstanding

anything in any other law contained, no Act of the Parliament

of the United Kingdom and Northern Ireland passed after

the eleventh day of December, 1931, shall extend, or be

deemed to extend, to the Union as part of the law of the

Union, unless extended thereto by an Act of the Parliament

of the Union."

But such a purely legal answer can easily be shown to be inade-

quate; for it does not explain what would happen if, to take Lord

Sankey's example, the United Kingdom Parliament were to attempt

to amend or repeal the Statute of Westminster. Most people would

predict, if they were willing to consider so unlikely an event,

that English judges would be bound to uphold the United Kingdom

Parliament's power to repeal or amend the Statute, 52 but that

South African judges would not. 53 The repealing Act would thus

be ineffective in South Africa, and the South African courts would

have thrown off their allegiance to the United Kingdom Parliament.

That means that a revolution has already taken place. Although

the South African courts acknowledge and obey the Status of the

Union Act, 1934, they cannot rely purely upon its legal pedigree:

for that in turn is derived from the Statute of Westminster, and

the Statute of Westminster in its own turn rests upon the authority

of the United Kingdom Parliament—the very authority which

South Africa has now repudiated. The more rational explanation

is that the South African courts have followed the movement

of political events, the movement summed up in the report of

the Imperial Conference which declared that the United Kingdom

and the Dominions were " in no way subordinate one to another

in any aspect of their domestic or external affairs,"5i and in

the defiant judicial dictum that " freedom once conferred cannot

be revoked." 55 The provision quoted from the Status of the

Union Act may be compared to the confirmatory Act of William

and Mary's Convention Parliament 50 —it states a political fact

which the courts also recognise. When sovereignty is relinquished

in an atmosphere of harmony, the naked fact of revolution is

not so easy to discern beneath its elaborate legal dress. But it

must be there just the same, and South Africa must have made

32 See Professor E. C. S. Wade's introduction to Dicey, 9th ed., xlviii; cf.
K. C. Wheare, The Statute of Westminster and Dominion Status, 5th ed
153-7, 246-7. 53 See Professor Cowen in 15 M.L. 294, note 47.
«: Cmd. 2768 (1926).
'j Note 14, above.
•> 6 1 Gul. & Mar. sess. 1, c. 1 (confirming Parliaments authority); 1 Gul. &
Mar. sess. 2, c. 2 (the Bill of Bights, 1689, confirming the title to the Crown).
Was this document helpful?
This is a Premium Document. Some documents on Studocu are Premium. Upgrade to Premium to unlock it.

The basis of legal sovereignty

Module: Contract Law (LAWS10021)

173 Documents
Students shared 173 documents in this course
Was this document helpful?

This is a preview

Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 26 pages
  • Access to all documents

  • Get Unlimited Downloads

  • Improve your grades

Upload

Share your documents to unlock

Already Premium?
THE BASIS
OF
LEGAL SOVEREIGNTY
H. W. R.
WADE
THE
great South African case
of
Harris
v.
Minister
of the
Interior1
will have turned
the
thoughts
of
many lawyers
to the
subject
of legal sovereignty. Under English
law the
principle
of the
sovereignty
of
Parliament,
" the
dominant characteristic
of our
political institutions,"
2 is
supposed
to be
something very simple
and clear—and
so
indeed
it
appears
in its
classic exposition
in
the pages
of
Dicey.
But the
classic exposition
is now
widely
controverted;
an
example
may be
taken from
the
recent remark
of
the
Lord President
of
the Court
of
Session
3:
" As
is
well known,
the
conflict between academic logic
and
political reality
has
been emphasised
by the
recent South
African decision
as to the
effect
of the
Statute
of
Westminster
Harris
v.
Minister of
the
Interior."
What
is
more,
on the
rare occasions when courts
in
England
or
the Commonwealth find themselves concerned with
the
validity
of Acts
of
Parliament, further conflicts
are
revealed
in the
comments
of text-writers
who
discuss these cases. There seems
to be a
widening rift between
the
orthodox propositions which
the
courts
lay down
and the
speculative deductions
of
critics
who
delve
deeper beneath
the
surface towards
the
bedrock
of
constitutional
theory. Inferences which
to
many people would seem
to be
1
1952 (2) S.A. 428; [1952] 1 T.L.E. 1245; Keir and Lawson Cases in Con-
stitutional Law (4th ed.) 506. For comment on the case see 68 L.Q.B.
285;
65 Harv.L.B. 1361; 30 Can.B.E. 692, 734; 31 Can.B.B. 52. After
losing this case the South African Government attempted to achieve its ends
by establishing special courts for such questions, since the legislature has
power to establish courts of law without recourse to the " entrenched " proce-
dure; but the Act constituting Parliament itself into such a court was held
illegal: Minister of the Interior v. Harris and Others, 1952 (4) S.A. 769.
The government has now procured legislation for increasing the number of
appellate judges and the number of Senators: Appeal Court Quorum Act,
1955;
Senate Act, 1955.
A most valuable commentary on the principal case will be found in
Professor D. V. Cowen's two articles on " Legislature and Judiciary " in
15 M.L.B. 282 and 16 M.L.E. 273, to which as will be seen the present
article is much indebted. Its object is not to survey further the voluminous
literature on sovereignty, but to attempt .to bring to a head the current
controversies on the subject. In a sense, therefore, it starts at the point
where Professor Cowen leaves off, for after his excellent account of the
background and the arguments of both sides he concludes that the fundamentals
of the subject are " fluid, elusive and obscure."
2
Dicey, Law of the Constitution (9th edition by Professor E. C. S. Wade), 39.
3
MacCormick
v.
Lord
Advocate,
1953 S.C. 396 at p. 412.
172
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0008197300013726 Published online by Cambridge University Press

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.

Why is this page out of focus?

This is a Premium document. Become Premium to read the whole document.