Skip to document

Mansueto Sprinkling - Grade: 1.0

Nietzsche and Religion
Course

Industrial Psychology

35 Documents
Students shared 35 documents in this course
Academic year: 2019/2020
Uploaded by:

Comments

Please sign in or register to post comments.

Preview text

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

SPRINGKLING SOME GRAINS OF THEISM WITH NIETZSCHE’S ATHEISTIC

DICTUM: “GOD IS DEAD”

Menelito P. Mansueto Holy Name University Tagbilaran City

Introduction

That “God is dead” is the first thing that would recall to mind the moment one invokes or mentions the name of Nietzsche, as if that’s the only thing people knew of him, that his name has become almost synonymous with atheism. In his lifetime, Nietzsche “murdered” God many times in his writings. In his The Gay Science (1882), he murdered God thrice; first, in section 108 that opens Book 3:

New struggles. – After Buddha was dead, his shadow was still shown for centuries in a cave – a tremendous, gruesome shadow. God is dead, but given the way of men, there may still be caves for thousands of years in which his shadow will be shown. – And we – we still have to vanquish his shadow, too 1.

Second, in section 125; here is an excerpt from that popular parable entitled, “The Madman”:

“Whither is God?” [the madman] cried: “I will tell you. We have killed him – you and I. All of us are his murderers... we hear nothing as yet of the noise of the gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as yet of the divine decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him 2.

And last, in section 343, which opens Book 5 (1887) 3 :

The background of our cheerfulness. The greatest recent event – that “God is dead,” that the belief in the Christian God has ceased to be believable – is even now beginning to cast its first shadows over Europe 4.

In the last quotation above, Nietzsche is even blithesome that God has “died”. There is no doubt regarding Nietzsche’s atheism. George Morgan even said, “beyond question the major premise of Nietzsche’s philosophy is atheism. 5 ” Had Nietzsche been an atheist without a purpose? Though he claimed he’s an atheist by instinct, 6 I still believe Nietzsche must have his reason for being so. Here I have figured out a dilemma. Supposing that a Nietzsche reader could not accept Nietzsche’s atheism should that be an obstacle to him/her in understanding Nietzsche’s thought? Especially that one can feel dread each time one hears of his “murderous” act. Should one give up reading him, especially that Nietzsche himself had intended that his writings should be “hard to understand” 7 and “not easy to penetrate” 8 because, accordingly, he chooses his readers and does not want to be read by just “anybody” 9. In fact, Nietzsche laments, according to Cowan, “he would rather not be understood because of the enormous suffering that must be the base for understanding him.” 10 Hence, if one does

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

not belong to his “kinship” – probably, an atheist, at that – one shall never be able to understand him. Kaufmann hits it bull’s eye when he wrote that Nietzsche is “the most misunderstood of all writers”.

OVERVIEW

Moving on, I shall defend a view that Nietzsche’s philosophy, despite being known to be largely atheistic, does not at all preclude an idea or a conception of a God – in a good sense of that. And so it follows that in understanding Nietzsche, one does not necessarily have to give up one’s belief in God, because in spite of Nietzsche’s atheistic claim, Nietzsche, too, simultaneously, can appear as a theist. What I shall do henceforth is to sneak in a conception of God through a backdoor amidst Nietzsche’s atheistic claims, and will try to describe what image of God would emerge. Though it can be so lenient and unusual, I ask the reader to permit this little experiment, after all, every person has his own understanding and conception of God – no one can dictate that to him – just as every religion does. The objective behind is I want to ward off the bias in understanding Nietzsche’s thought. For such a bias could deter one from reading and understanding a great mind (and soul, too) in the twentieth century philosophical thought. I declare that although Nietzsche is against Christianity, he is never totally against God. This will serve as an invitation to look at Nietzsche’s thought from the perspective in the opposite side of the spectrum: Nietzsche as theist. I shall first establish Nietzsche’s merit as an atheist philosopher for us to understand why so narrow and confined a conception of God that will prevail later on. This will be discussed in three parts, namely: (1) Nietzsche’s view on the “metaphysical need” of man; (2) his view of morality; and (3) his concept of the “amor fati.”

NIETZSCHE’S MERIT AS AN ATHEIST

For more than a century now after his insanity and death, one cannot deny that Nietzsche remained a very interesting and influential thinker of the twentieth century, ranging his influences from the literature to the philosophical arena, despite his atheistic stance on various subjects. Often regarded to be a precursor of the twentieth century in the sense that he anticipated what is now part of the consciousness of every thinking man and woman. From his atheistic standpoint, Nietzsche could bring his reader a tour on various aspects regarding man’s religiosity, morality, and life.

(1) Nietzsche’s View on the “Metaphysical Need” of Man

This is Nietzsche’s view of man that one can find in section 347 of his The Gay Science, it reads as follows: “For this is how man is: An article of faith could be refuted before him a thousand times – if he needed it, he would consider it ‘true’ again and again.” 11 Here, Nietzsche speaks of the “metaphysical need” of man. He argued that man needed a faith to “flourish”. A faith that is “firm” because man “clings to it” and that he does not want to be “shaken”. In fact, according to Nietzsche, this faith becomes the measure of man’s strength 12. Why Nietzsche wishes to deny man his God is obvious – he wants to see man, the faithful, crumble into his feet. For, according to Nietzsche, what was once regarded as man’s strength

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

as, pity, sympathy, humility, patience, kindness, warm-heartedness, and etc. were considered good virtues by the slaves for these are, Nietzsche says, the most useful qualities and virtually the only means of enduring the burden of existence.

Nietzsche, however, pointed out that these two moralities can dwell together “within a single soul”, within the same person at the same time. 21 In his On the Genealogy of Morals, Nietzsche furthers his analysis, of how ressentiment – that instinct for revenge “turns inward” and develops into what he calls a “bad conscience” 22. And of how “bad conscience gave birth into a God by way of having projected someone who could free them from their sufferings – they illusion a God. 23

Nietzsche makes fun of comparing the slaves into a “herd”. Like herd-animals, slaves herd themselves into groups that need to be commanded like a sheep who follows other sheep. Nietzsche also refers to the master as “beasts of prey.” Similarly, the Scripture, particularly the New Testament, often refers to the faithful as “a flock”, with God as their shepherd. There is no surprise that Nietzsche would be inclined to suggest that Christian morality is “inherently structured as a form of slave morality.” 24 Characterizing man as a herd-animal, “tame”, “sickly”, and “weak”, Nietzsche has come to regard morality as a disguise, a shield, a weapon against the ferocious “beasts of prey”. A passage in Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra will best capture this point: “I have often laughed at the weaklings who thought themselves good because they have no claws” 25. Instead of revealing oneself as a weak creature without claws, “one pretends that one is ferocious and that only a high regard for morality” can keep foes from doing terrible things 26.

(3) Nietzsche’s Concept of “Amor Fati”

The year before his collapse in 1889 in a street in Turin and to which later recovered but was then diagnosed of a “general paralysis of the insane”, Nietzsche amazingly completed six books in one year despite a “continued ill health and excruciating physical pain” 27 due to an infection of syphilis 28. And as to how has he endured living that kind of life, his answer was simple: “what does not kill me makes me stronger” 29. This could mean the manner he “cure” his illness is through work. In other words, sickness did not stop him, it even compelled him to work. 30

This shows how relevant is Nietzsche’s own life in understanding his conception of “amor fati” because it should be understood, too, what kind of life Nietzsche had lived, in which case, a life of “day-to-day” battle with illness. He wrote in Ecce Homo: “Never have I felt happier with myself than in the sickest and most painful periods of my life” 31. Amor fati is from Latin which literally means “love of fate”. Or simply said, it is a person’s love of one’s life, with all its defects, it’s “flaws”, just for what it is 32.

To add impact on this, I include Nietzsche’s “doctrine” of the eternal recurrence of the same events. In the section 341 of The Gay Science, Nietzsche asks the reader to imagine what if one day or night a “demon” would appear to him/her in his/her loneliest hour and say. “This life as you now live it and have lived it, you will have to live once more and innumerable times more; and there will be nothing new in it, but every pain and every joy and

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

every thought and sigh and everything unutterably small or great in your life will have to return to you, all in the same succession and sequence – even this spider and this moonlight between the trees, and even this moment and I myself. The eternal hourglass of existence is turned upside down again and again, and you with it, speck of dust!” 33 Then, Nietzsche goes on by asking the reader what would be his/her response to it- see yourself if you pass this psycho-test!

Normally, when one is asked if given the chance to live one’s life again, responses will vary such as having a different kind of life, or, to a sort of a revised version of that life. But, to live again an exactly the same life as one had already lived, down to its tiny details again and again. – takes enough courage to give a positive response, honestly!

Indeed, a daring ‘Yes’ could serve as a testimony of how much one considers one’s own life as valuable, meaningful, and worthy of living it over and over again. 34 Nietzsche considers this doctrine of eternal recurrence as the highest affirmation of life, a manifestation of one’s amor fati.

A firm ‘Yes’ means that one takes one’s own life as it is, because it is actually just one’s same life posted as another that one has affirmed – a nasty trick! To affirm life means to accept one’s life as one’s own – that is, to own one’s life. Only then can one be inclined to live more, to “thirst” more of that life, to keep wanting for that life. Regardless of whether Nietzsche had seriously believed his theory of the eternal recurrence, one thing certain is that it provides an “existential imperative”, an existential meaning in every person’s life.

“ALAS, A LIGHT CREEPS IN!”

Now as to whether God could fit in the picture, I shall draw my analysis only from what I have presented above. First, I shall determine the conception of God to which Nietzsche abhors, then, based on that, I shall furnish a conception of God to which Nietzsche cannot possibly abhor; if so, otherwise, I shall find Nietzsche contradicting his own position.

Based on Nietzsche’s view of the “metaphysical need” of man, I presented a view of God to which Nietzsche considers a fantasy that could redeem man from disgrace; also, a God which is a healer that alleviates man’s pain and suffering. In short, God is a remedy that heals or covers up man’s weakness.

In Nietzsche’s view of morality, I presented a view of God to which Nietzsche considers as a weapon and shield to cover up man’s inadequacies. This includes the view of God as a defender, protector, and savior that delivers man from harm. Purely conceived, God as remedy and weapon against man’s weakness only caters man everything that satisfies him to fill in his inadequacies. Nietzsche contends that such a God, or more precisely, idea of such a God should be “murdered” for reasons that it makes man dependent and “surrenders his power to God” 35 , that such an idea of a God could only make man more helpless and weak. In short, such a God hinders man from realizing his power inherent in him.

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

What have I done! I have rescued God under Nietzsche’s knife, at the same time that I cleansed Nietzsche’s hands, like an angel who appeared and rescued Isaac from Abraham’s hands. Is it necessarily God’s fault if God’s very own people would misconstrue God? Does God have a choice (hence, the title) if man would consider God as the solution to his sufferings? What more could God do supposing that God has created for man the best possible world that God could ever create – this world which is, yet, unfortunately, known for being an imperfect world. Can God be the culprit to blame?

An astute reader may be able to refute at once our ardent picture of God as the life- giver. Here, too, I will refute myself for the reader’s benefit. Supposing that man himself will find that gift – his own life – as worthless: a life in this world full of struggles and hardships, with its poverty and pain, will most likely bring one to an exhaustion up to a point of saying: “I don’t want this life anymore!” and more so: “What kind of God who will give us as a gift a wicked and cruel life?” – What will be Nietzsche’s answer to that? To the first objection, surely, I remain firm that it’s still the amor fati – the eternal recurrence of the same events – which is a constant affirmation and re-affirmation of life in this world, a positive attitude towards that life. To the second: Life in this world with its opposing features that are intertwined toward its necessary opposite: joy with pain, triumph with loss, or, what Nietzsche simply called “the wedding of dark and light” 39. “[P]leasure and pain,” wrote Nietzsche, “were so linked together that he who wants to have the greatest possible amount of the one must have the greatest possible amount of the other also” 40 It should be understood then that man, having such a condition of life, will naturally feel, just as he could express his reverence to a God, that he could as well express his irreverence to that same God. These are all part of life.

I do hope I’ve given a fair treatment in showing the significance of Nietzsche’s denial of any metaphysical reality, such as the “beyond”, “other world”, “after-world”, “after-life” and even God, in favor of a concrete earthly existence and life. Nietzsche has sacrificed God for his love of man. He has denied God to give the “greatest weight” on human life. He might have realized that the best way to give emphasis on life is to “murder” that very being which has caused man’s misunderstanding of himself. I say that Nietzsche is not a full-blown atheist but a full-blown humanist. He wrote in Zarathustra: “I love man” and “I bring men a gift,” 41 and, I think, that could sum up his atheism. Lastly, I’d like to take note that the image of God which Nietzsche rejects is closer to the image of God in the New Testament. For additional knowledge, Nietzsche has “the highest admiration” to the Old Testament 42. A passage in Section 52 of his Beyond Good and Evil expresses hi s distaste to the New Testament in preference to the Old Testament: “To have glued this New Testament, a kind of rococo of taste in every respect, to the Old Testament to form one book.. is perhaps the greatest audacity and ‘sin against the spirit’ that literary Europe has on its conscience.”

As with regards to my task, I am fully aware how inappropriate it is to ascribe to Nietzsche what does not belong to Nietzsche. It even amounts to accusing him of the very things he loathed. But isn’t it equally inappropriate to deny him of such things merely because he does not have it? And regarding the accusation of Nietzsche’s emerging from the dark side, I take Henrik Ibsen’s 43 words defending Nietzsche in an interview: “Satan – no. No,

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

Nietzsche wasn’t that” 44. Nietzsche’s thought has not emerged from the dark side, I have just shown you how a light creeps in.

Before ending this, I would like Nietzsche to have his final say:

Indeed, people will have trouble understanding us... are we anyway? If we simply call ourselves, using an old expression, godless, or unbelievers, or perhaps immoralists, we do not believe that this would even come close to designating us: We are all three in such an advanced stage that one – that you, my curious friends – could never comprehend how we feel at this point... know it well, the world in which we live is ungodly, immoral, “inhuman”; we have interpreted it far too long in a false and mendacious way, in accordance with the wishes of our reverence, which is to say, according to our needs... are far from claiming that the world is worth less: indeed it would seem laughable to us today if man were to insist on inventing values that were supposed to excel the value of the actual world. This is precisely what we have turned our backs on as an extravagant aberration of human vanity and unreason that for a long time was not recognized as such. 45

Conclusion

These are the conclusions drawn from the preceding presentation: Atheism is necessary, but not a requirement, in understanding Nietzsche’s thoughts. Nietzsche regards faith in God as a form of hypnotism and fanaticism. Nietzsche strips off man’s faith in God to expose his weakness. According to Nietzsche; man’s suffering led to the invention of God. God is the solution to man’s inadequacies. God is a weapon that covers up man’s weakness. God makes man dependent and weakens his power. Amor Fati is a person’s love of one’s life, with all its flaws, just as what it is. According to Nietzsche, the eternal recurrence is the highest possible affirmation of life and the manifestation of amor fati. Nietzsche is a philosopher devoted to life. Nietzsche has denied God’s existence to give more value on human life. A life-giving God, however, is reconcilable into Nietzsche’s thought.

Endnotes

1 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, tr. with commentary by Walter Kaufmann

(New York: Vintage Books, 1974), p. 2 Ibid., p. 3 Book 5 was added to the second edition in 1887. 4 Ibid., p.

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

25 Friedrich Nietzsche. Thus Spoke Zarathustra (New York: The Modern Library,

1995), p. 26 Nietzsche. The Gay Science, p. 27 Nietzsche. Basic Writings, p. 28 R. Hollingdale. Nietzsche: The Man and His Philosophy. (Cambridge University

Press, 1999), p. 29 Ibid., p. 30 Ibid., p. See also ibid., p. 31 Nietzsche. Basic Writings, p. 32 Bernd Magnus and Kathleen M. Higgins. Cambridge Companion, p. 33 Nietzsche. The Gay Science, pp-274. 34 Bernd Magnus and Kathleen M. Higgins. Cambridge Companion, p. 35 Eddie R. Babor. “Nietzsche’s Concept of Religious” in Philosophia, International

Journal of Philosophy, (De La Salle University, Vol. 34, 2: 2005), p. 36 Nietzsche. The Gay Science, p. 37 Ibid. 38 “The fear of the ancestor and his power, the consciousness of indebtedness to him,

increases, according to this kind of logic.... If one imagines this rude kind of logic carried to its end, then the ancestors of the most powerful tribes are bound eventually to grow to monstrous dimensions through the imagination of growing fear.. the end the ancestor must necessarily be transfigured into a god. Perhaps this is even the origin of gods, an origin therefore out of fear!” Nietzsche. Basic Writings, p. 39 Ibid., p. 40 R. Hollingdale. Nietzsche: The Man and His Philosophy, p. 41 Nietzsche. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p. 42 Kaufmann. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, p. 43 Henrik Ibsen, a Norwegian poet and playwright. 44 Friedrich Nietzsche. The Will to Power (New York: Vintage Books, 1968), pp-

  1. 45 Nietzsche. The Gay Science, pp-286.

Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines

Bibliography

Babor, Eddie R. “Nietzsche’s Concept of Religious” in Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy. De La Salle University. Vol. 34, 2:2005.

_____________. Introduction, in Ethics: The Philosophical Discipline of Action. Manila: Rex Book Store, 1999.

Cowan, Marianne. Introduction, in Beyond Good and Evil, by Friedrich Nietzsche. Chicago: Gateway Edition, 1955.

Hollingdale, R. Nietzsche: The Man and His Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Kaufmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. 4th ed. New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1974.

Magnus Bernd and Kathleen M. Higgins, eds. The Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche. Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Basic Writings of Nietzsche, tr. and edited, with Commentaries, by Walter Kaufmann. New York: The Modern Library, 1997.

________________. The Gay Science, translated, with Commentary, by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1074.

________________. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, translated with a Preface by Walter Kaufmann. New York: The Modern Library, 1995.

________________. The Will to Power, translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage Books, 1968.

Was this document helpful?

Mansueto Sprinkling - Grade: 1.0

Course: Industrial Psychology

35 Documents
Students shared 35 documents in this course
Was this document helpful?
LUMINA An Interdisciplinary Research and Scholarly Journal Vol. 20 Vol.20, No.1 March 2009
Holy Name University, Tagbilaran City, Bohol, Philippines
SPRINGKLING SOME GRAINS OF THEISM WITH NIETZSCHE’S ATHEISTIC
DICTUM: “GOD IS DEAD”
Menelito P. Mansueto
Holy Name University
Tagbilaran City
Introduction
That “God is dead” is the first thing that would recall to mind the moment one invokes
or mentions the name of Nietzsche, as if that’s the only thing people knew of him, that his
name has become almost synonymous with atheism. In his lifetime, Nietzsche “murdered”
God many times in his writings. In his The Gay Science (1882), he murdered God thrice; first,
in section 108 that opens Book 3:
New struggles. After Buddha was dead, his shadow was still shown for
centuries in a cave a tremendous, gruesome shadow. God is dead, but given
the way of men, there may still be caves for thousands of years in which his
shadow will be shown. – And we – we still have to vanquish his shadow, too
1
.
Second, in section 125; here is an excerpt from that popular parable entitled, “The Madman”:
“Whither is God?” [the madman] cried: “I will tell you. We have killed him
you and I. All of us are his murderers….Do we hear nothing as yet of the noise
of the gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as yet of the
divine decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. God remains dead.
And we have killed him
2
.
And last, in section 343, which opens Book 5 (1887)
3
:
The background of our cheerfulness. The greatest recent event that “God is
dead,” that the belief in the Christian God has ceased to be believable is even
now beginning to cast its first shadows over Europe
4
.
In the last quotation above, Nietzsche is even blithesome that God has “died”. There is no
doubt regarding Nietzsche’s atheism. George Morgan even said, “beyond question the major
premise of Nietzsche’s philosophy is atheism.
5
Had Nietzsche been an atheist without a
purpose? Though he claimed he’s an atheist by instinct,
6
I still believe Nietzsche must have
his reason for being so. Here I have figured out a dilemma. Supposing that a Nietzsche reader
could not accept Nietzsche’s atheism should that be an obstacle to him/her in understanding
Nietzsche’s thought? Especially that one can feel dread each time one hears of his
“murderous” act. Should one give up reading him, especially that Nietzsche himself had
intended that his writings should be “hard to understand”
7
and “not easy to penetrate”
8
because, accordingly, he chooses his readers and does not want to be read by just “anybody”
9
.
In fact, Nietzsche laments, according to Cowan, “he would rather not be understood because
of the enormous suffering that must be the base for understanding him.”
10
Hence, if one does